Library HoTT.Universes.Smallness

Facts about "small" types

This closely follows Section 2 of the paper "Non-accessible localizations", by Dan Christensen, https://arxiv.org/abs/2109.06670
Universe variables: we most often use a subset of i j k u. We think of Type@{i} as containing the "small" types and Type@{j} the "large" types. In some early results, there are no constraints between i and j, and in others we require that i j, as expected. While the case i = j isn't particularly interesting, we put some effort into ensuring that it is permitted as well, as there is no semantic reason to exclude it. The universe variable k should be thought of as max(i+1,j), and it is generally required to satisfy i < k and j k. If we assume that i < j, then we can take k = j, but we include k so that we also allow the case i = j. The universe variable u is only present because we occasionally use Univalence in Type@{k}, so the equality types need a larger universe to live in. Because of this, most results require k < u.
Summary of the most common situation: i < k < u, j k, where i is for the small types, j is for the large types, k = max(i+1,j) and u is an ambient universe for Univalence.
We include universe annotations when they clarify the meaning (e.g. in IsSmall and when using PropResizing), and also when it is required in order to keep control of the universe variables.
Note that IsSmall is defined in Overture.v.

Global Instance ishprop_issmall@{i j k | i < k, jk}
  `{Univalence} (X : Type@{j})
  : IsHProp (IsSmall@{i j} X).
Proof.
  apply hprop_inhabited_contr.
  intros [Z e].
  (* IsSmall X is equivalent to IsSmall Z, which is contractible since it is a based path space. *)
  rapply (istrunc_equiv_istrunc { Y : Type@{i} & Y <~> Z } _).
  equiv_via (sig@{k k} (fun Y : Type@{i} ⇒ Y <~> X)).
  2: issig.
  apply equiv_functor_sigma_id.
  intro Y.
  exact (equiv_functor_postcompose_equiv Y e).
Defined.

A type in Type@{i} is clearly small.
Global Instance issmall_in@{i j | ij} (X : Type@{i}) : IsSmall@{i j} X | 10
  := Build_IsSmall X X equiv_idmap.

The small types are closed under equivalence.
Definition issmall_equiv_issmall@{i1 j1 i2 j2 | i1i2} {A : Type@{j1}} {B : Type@{j2}}
  (e : A <~> B) (sA : IsSmall@{i1 j1} A)
  : IsSmall@{i2 j2} B.
Proof.
   (smalltype A).
  exact (e oE (equiv_smalltype A)).
Defined.

The small types are closed under dependent sums.
Definition sigma_closed_issmall@{i j | } {A : Type@{j}}
  (B : A Type@{j}) (sA : IsSmall@{i j} A)
  (sB : a, IsSmall@{i j} (B a))
  : IsSmall@{i j} { a : A & B a }.
Proof.
   { a : (smalltype A) & (smalltype (B (equiv_smalltype A a))) }.
  snrapply equiv_functor_sigma'; intros; apply equiv_smalltype.
Defined.

If a map has small codomain and fibers, then the domain is small.
Definition issmall_issmall_codomain_fibers@{i j | } {X Y : Type@{j}}
  (f : X Y)
  (sY : IsSmall@{i j} Y)
  (sF : y : Y, IsSmall@{i j} (hfiber f y))
  : IsSmall@{i j} X.
Proof.
  nrapply issmall_equiv_issmall.
  - exact (equiv_fibration_replacement f)^-1%equiv.
  - apply sigma_closed_issmall; assumption.
Defined.

Every contractible type is small.
Definition issmall_contr@{i j| } (X : Type@{j}) (T : Contr X)
  : IsSmall@{i j} X
  := issmall_equiv_issmall (equiv_contr_unit)^-1 _.

If we can show that X is small when it is inhabited, then it is in fact small. This is Remark 2.9 in the paper. It lets us simplify the statement of Proposition 2.8. Note that this implies propositional resizing, so the PropResizing assumption is necessary.
Definition issmall_inhabited_issmall@{i j k | i < k, jk} `{PropResizing} `{Univalence}
  (X : Type@{j})
  (isX : X IsSmall@{i j} X)
  : IsSmall@{i j} X.
Proof.
  (* Since IsSmall is cumulative in the universe j, it suffices to prove IsSmall@{i k} X for k the universe that IsSmall@{i j} lives in.  We think of k as max(i+1,j). *)
  rapply (issmall_issmall_codomain_fibers@{i k} isX).
  intro sX.
  rapply sigma_closed_issmall.
Defined.

If a type X is truncated, then so is smalltype X.
Global Instance istrunc_smalltype@{i j | } (X : Type@{j}) (n : trunc_index)
  `{IsSmall@{i j} X, IsTrunc n X}
  : IsTrunc n (smalltype X)
  := istrunc_equiv_istrunc X (equiv_smalltype@{i j} X)^-1%equiv.

Locally small types

We say that a type X is 0-locally small if it is small, and (n+1)-locally small if its identity types are n-locally small.
(* TODO: Can we make this an inductive type and avoid the extra universe variable k? *)
Fixpoint IsLocallySmall@{i j k | i < k, jk} (n : nat) (X : Type@{j}) : Type@{k}
  := match n with
    | 0%natIsSmall@{i j} X
    | S m x y : X, IsLocallySmall m (x = y)
    end.
Existing Class IsLocallySmall.
Hint Unfold IsLocallySmall : typeclass_instances.

Global Instance ishprop_islocallysmall@{i j k | i < k, jk} `{Univalence}
  (n : nat) (X : Type@{j})
  : IsHProp@{k} (IsLocallySmall@{i j k} n X).
Proof.
  (* Here and later we use simple_induction to control the universe variable. *)
  revert X; simple_induction n n IHn; exact _.
Defined.

A small type is n-locally small for all n.
Global Instance islocallysmall_in@{i j k | ij, jk, i < k}
  (n : nat) (X : Type@{i})
  : IsLocallySmall@{i j k} n X.
Proof.
  revert X.
  induction n; intro X.
  - apply issmall_in.
  - intros x y.
    exact (IHn (x = y)).
Defined.

The n-locally small types are closed under equivalence.
Definition islocallysmall_equiv_islocallysmall
  @{i j1 j2 k | i < k, j1k, j2k}
  (n : nat) {A : Type@{j1}} {B : Type@{j2}}
  (e : A <~> B) (lsA : IsLocallySmall@{i j1 k} n A)
  : IsLocallySmall@{i j2 k} n B.
Proof.
  revert A B e lsA.
  simple_induction n n IHn.
  - exact @issmall_equiv_issmall.
  - intros A B e lsA b b'.
    nrapply IHn.
    × exact (equiv_ap' (e^-1%equiv) b b')^-1%equiv.
    × apply lsA.
Defined.

A small type is n-locally small for all n.
Global Instance islocallysmall_issmall@{i j k | i < k, jk} (n : nat)
  (X : Type@{j}) (sX : IsSmall@{i j} X)
  : IsLocallySmall@{i j k} n X
  := islocallysmall_equiv_islocallysmall n (equiv_smalltype X) _.

If a type is n-locally small, then it is (n+1)-locally small.
Global Instance islocallysmall_succ@{i j k | i < k, jk} (n : nat)
  (X : Type@{j}) (lsX : IsLocallySmall@{i j k} n X)
  : IsLocallySmall@{i j k} n.+1 X.
Proof.
  revert X lsX; simple_induction n n IHn; intros X.
  - apply islocallysmall_issmall.
  - intro lsX.
    intros x y.
    apply IHn, lsX.
Defined.

The n-locally small types are closed under dependent sums.
Global Instance sigma_closed_islocallysmall@{i j k | i < k, jk}
  (n : nat) {A : Type@{j}} (B : A Type@{j})
  (lsA : IsLocallySmall@{i j k} n A)
  (lsB : a, IsLocallySmall@{i j k} n (B a))
  : IsLocallySmall@{i j k} n { a : A & B a }.
Proof.
  revert A B lsA lsB.
  simple_induction n n IHn.
  - exact @sigma_closed_issmall.
  - intros A B lsA lsB x y.
    apply (islocallysmall_equiv_islocallysmall n (equiv_path_sigma _ x y)).
    apply IHn.
    × apply lsA.
    × intro p.
      apply lsB.
Defined.

If a map has n-locally small codomain and fibers, then the domain is n-locally small.
Definition islocallysmall_islocallysmall_codomain_fibers@{i j k | i < k, jk}
  (n : nat) {X Y : Type@{j}} (f : X Y)
  (sY : IsLocallySmall@{i j k} n Y)
  (sF : y : Y, IsLocallySmall@{i j k} n (hfiber f y))
  : IsLocallySmall@{i j k} n X.
Proof.
  nrapply islocallysmall_equiv_islocallysmall.
  - exact (equiv_fibration_replacement f)^-1%equiv.
  - apply sigma_closed_islocallysmall; assumption.
Defined.

Under propositional resizing, every (n+1)-truncated type is (n+2)-locally small. This is Lemma 2.3 in the paper.
Global Instance islocallysmall_trunc@{i j k | i < k, jk} `{PropResizing}
  (n : trunc_index) (X : Type@{j}) (T : IsTrunc n.+1 X)
  : IsLocallySmall@{i j k} (trunc_index_to_nat n) X.
Proof.
  revert n X T.
  simple_induction n n IHn; cbn.
  - nrapply issmall_hprop@{i j}.
  - intros X T x y.
    rapply IHn.
Defined.